Martin Escardo, March 2022 This generalizes the 2018 file OrdinalNotationInterpretation1. A Tarski universe E of ordinal codes with two related decoding functions Δ and Κ (standing for "discrete" and "compact" respectively). Roughly speaking, E gives ordinal codes or expressions denoting infinite ordinals. The expressions themselves are infinitary. An ordinal is a type equipped with an order _≺_ that satisfies suitable properties, which in particular imply that the type is a set in the sense of HoTT/UF. The adopted notion of ordinal is that of the HoTT book. For a code ν : E, we have an ordinal Δ ν, which is discrete (has decidable equality). For a code ν : E, we have an ordinal Κ ν, which is compact (or "searchable"). More than that, every complemented subset of Κ ν is either empty or has a minimal element. There is an embedding ι : Δ ν → Κ ν which is order preserving and reflecting, and whose image has empty complement. The assumption that it is a bijection implies LPO. This extends and generalizes OrdinalNotationInterpretation1, for which slides for a talk are available at https://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~mhe/.talks/csl2022.pdf which may well serve as an introduction to this file. The main difference is that the ordinal expressions considered there amount to a W type, whereas the ones considered here amount to an inductive-recursive type, generalizing that, which is explained in these slides https://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~mhe/.talks/ljubljana2022.pdf This is a draft version that needs polishing and more explanation. \begin{code} {-# OPTIONS --safe --without-K #-} open import MLTT.Spartan open import UF.FunExt module Ordinals.NotationInterpretation2 (fe : FunExt) where private fe₀ = fe 𝓤₀ 𝓤₀ open import CoNaturals.Type open import MLTT.Two-Properties open import Naturals.Binary hiding (_+_) open import Notation.CanonicalMap hiding (ι) open import Ordinals.Arithmetic fe open import Ordinals.Closure fe open import Ordinals.Equivalence open import Ordinals.InfProperty open import Ordinals.Injectivity open import Ordinals.ToppedArithmetic fe open import Ordinals.ToppedType fe open import Ordinals.Type open import Ordinals.Underlying open import Taboos.LPO open import Taboos.WLPO open import TypeTopology.CompactTypes open import TypeTopology.Density open import TypeTopology.FailureOfTotalSeparatedness open import TypeTopology.LimitPoints open import TypeTopology.PropInfTychonoff fe open import TypeTopology.SigmaDiscreteAndTotallySeparated open import UF.DiscreteAndSeparated open import UF.Embeddings open import UF.Equiv open import UF.PairFun open import UF.Retracts open import UF.Subsingletons \end{code} We define E and Δ by simultaneous induction. The type Ordᵀ is that of ordinals with a top element (classically, successor ordinals). Recall that ⟨ α ⟩ is the underlying type of α : Ordᵀ. \begin{code} data E : 𝓤₀ ̇ Δ : E → Ordᵀ data E where ⌜𝟙⌝ : E ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ : E _⌜+⌝_ : E → E → E _⌜×⌝_ : E → E → E ⌜Σ⌝ : (ν : E) → (⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → E) → E Δ ⌜𝟙⌝ = 𝟙ᵒ Δ ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = succₒ ω Δ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = Δ ν₀ +ᵒ Δ ν₁ Δ (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = Δ ν₀ ×ᵒ Δ ν₁ Δ (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = ∑ (Δ ν) (Δ ∘ A) \end{code} The underlying sets of all ordinals in the image of Δ are retracts of ℕ and hence countable. \begin{code} Δ-retract-of-ℕ : (ν : E) → retract ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ of ℕ Δ-retract-of-ℕ ⌜𝟙⌝ = (λ _ → ⋆) , (λ _ → 0) , 𝟙-is-prop ⋆ Δ-retract-of-ℕ ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ≃-gives-◁ ℕ-plus-𝟙 Δ-retract-of-ℕ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = Σ-retract-of-ℕ retract-𝟙+𝟙-of-ℕ (dep-cases (λ _ → Δ-retract-of-ℕ ν₀) (λ _ → Δ-retract-of-ℕ ν₁)) Δ-retract-of-ℕ (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = Σ-retract-of-ℕ (Δ-retract-of-ℕ ν₀) (λ _ → Δ-retract-of-ℕ ν₁) Δ-retract-of-ℕ (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = Σ-retract-of-ℕ (Δ-retract-of-ℕ ν) (λ x → Δ-retract-of-ℕ (A x)) \end{code} Hence all ordinals in the image of Δ are discrete (have decidable equality). \begin{code} Δ-is-discrete : (ν : E) → is-discrete ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ Δ-is-discrete ν = retract-is-discrete (Δ-retract-of-ℕ ν) ℕ-is-discrete \end{code} A stronger result is that the ordinals in the image of Δ are trichotomous: \begin{code} Δ-is-trichotomous : (ν : E) → is-trichotomous [ Δ ν ] Δ-is-trichotomous ⌜𝟙⌝ = 𝟙ₒ-is-trichotomous Δ-is-trichotomous ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = succₒ-is-trichotomous ω ω-is-trichotomous Δ-is-trichotomous (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = +ᵒ-is-trichotomous (Δ ν₀) (Δ ν₁) (Δ-is-trichotomous ν₀) (Δ-is-trichotomous ν₁) Δ-is-trichotomous (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = ×ᵒ-is-trichotomous (Δ ν₀) (Δ ν₁) (Δ-is-trichotomous ν₀) (Δ-is-trichotomous ν₁) Δ-is-trichotomous (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = ∑-is-trichotomous (Δ ν) (Δ ∘ A) (Δ-is-trichotomous ν) (Δ-is-trichotomous ∘ A) \end{code} Now we define Κ, ι, ι-is-embedding by simultaneous induction. \begin{code} Κ : E → Ordᵀ ι : (ν : E) → ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ ι-is-embedding : (ν : E) → is-embedding (ι ν) \end{code} Before completing the induction, we define the following abbreviation. \begin{code} j : (ν : E) → ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ ↪ ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ j ν = ι ν , ι-is-embedding ν \end{code} We use the following auxiliary extension constructions, illustrated by this diagram ι ν ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ ⟶ ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ | . | . A | . (K ∘ A) ↗ j ν | . ↓ ↓ E ⟶ Ordᵀ Κ See the files ToppedOrdinalArithmetic and InjectiveTypes for details. \begin{code} open topped-ordinals-injectivity fe 𝓚 : (ν : E) → (⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → E) → ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ → Ordᵀ 𝓚 ν A = (Κ ∘ A) ↗ j ν \end{code} Explicitly, the underlying set of this ordinal is given as follows in the file InjectiveTypes. \begin{code} _ : (ν : E) (A : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → E) (y : ⟨ Κ ν ⟩) → ⟨ 𝓚 ν A y ⟩ = (Π (x , _) ꞉ fiber (ι ν) y , ⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩) _ = λ ν A y → refl \end{code} The above gives an extension up to ordinal equivalence \begin{code} module Κ-extension (ν : E) (A : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → E) where ϕ : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] ≃ₒ [ Κ (A x) ] ϕ = ↗-propertyₒ (Κ ∘ A) (j ν) φ : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ → ⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ φ x = ≃ₒ-to-fun [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (ϕ x) γ : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ → ⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ γ x = ≃ₒ-to-fun⁻¹ [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (ϕ x) φ-is-equiv : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → is-equiv (φ x) φ-is-equiv x = ≃ₒ-to-fun-is-equiv [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (ϕ x) γ-is-equiv : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → is-equiv (γ x) γ-is-equiv x = ≃ₒ-to-fun⁻¹-is-equiv [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (ϕ x) Γ : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ ≃ ⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ Γ x = γ x , γ-is-equiv x Κ ⌜𝟙⌝ = 𝟙ᵒ Κ ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ℕ∞ᵒ Κ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = Κ ν₀ +ᵒ Κ ν₁ Κ (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = Κ ν₀ ×ᵒ Κ ν₁ Κ (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = ∑ (Κ ν) (𝓚 ν A) ι ⌜𝟙⌝ = id ι ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ι𝟙 ι (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun id (dep-cases (λ _ → ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁)) ι (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun (ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁) ι (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = pair-fun (ι ν) (λ x → γ x ∘ ι (A x)) where open Κ-extension ν A ι-is-embedding ⌜𝟙⌝ = id-is-embedding ι-is-embedding ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ι𝟙-is-embedding fe₀ ι-is-embedding (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-embedding id (dep-cases (λ _ → ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁)) id-is-embedding (dep-cases (λ _ → ι-is-embedding ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-embedding ν₁)) ι-is-embedding (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-embedding _ _ (ι-is-embedding ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-embedding ν₁) ι-is-embedding (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = pair-fun-is-embedding _ _ (ι-is-embedding ν) (λ x → ∘-is-embedding (ι-is-embedding (A x)) (equivs-are-embeddings' (Γ x))) where open Κ-extension ν A \end{code} This completes the definitions of Κ, ι and ι-is-embedding. The important fact about the Κ interpretation is that the ordinals in its image have the least element property for non-empty complemented subsets, and, in particular, they are compact, and more generally infs of arbitrary complemented subsets. \begin{code} module _ (pe : propext 𝓤₀) where K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets : (ν : E) → has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (Κ ν) 𝓚-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets : (ν : E) (A : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → E) (x : ⟨ Κ ν ⟩) → has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (𝓚 ν A x) K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ⌜𝟙⌝ = 𝟙ᵒ-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ℕ∞ᵒ-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets pe K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = ∑-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets pe 𝟚ᵒ (cases (λ _ → Κ ν₀) (λ _ → Κ ν₁)) 𝟚ᵒ-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (dep-cases (λ _ → K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν₀) (λ _ → K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν₁)) K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = ∑-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets pe (Κ ν₀) (λ _ → Κ ν₁) (K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν₀) (λ _ → K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν₁) K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = ∑-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets pe (Κ ν) (𝓚 ν A) (K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν) (𝓚-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν A) 𝓚-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν A x = prop-inf-tychonoff (ι-is-embedding ν x) (λ {(x , _)} y z → y ≺⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ z) (λ (x , _) → K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets (A x)) \end{code} And, as discussed above, as a corollary we get that the ordinals in the image of Κ are compact. \begin{code} Κ-Compact : {𝓥 : Universe} (ν : E) → is-Compact ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ {𝓥} Κ-Compact ν = has-inf-gives-Compact _ (K-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν) 𝓚-Compact : {𝓥 : Universe} (ν : E) (A : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → E) (x : ⟨ Κ ν ⟩) → is-Compact ⟨ 𝓚 ν A x ⟩ {𝓥} 𝓚-Compact ν A x = has-inf-gives-Compact _ (𝓚-has-infs-of-complemented-subsets ν A x) \end{code} The embedding of the Δ interpretation into the Κ interpretation is order-preserving, order-reflecting, and dense (its image has empty complement). \begin{code} ι-is-order-preserving : (ν : E) (x y : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → x ≺⟨ Δ ν ⟩ y → ι ν x ≺⟨ Κ ν ⟩ ι ν y ι-is-order-preserving ⌜𝟙⌝ = λ x y l → l ι-is-order-preserving ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ι𝟙ᵒ-is-order-preserving ι-is-order-preserving (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-order-preserving 𝟚ᵒ 𝟚ᵒ (cases (λ _ → Δ ν₀) (λ _ → Δ ν₁)) (cases (λ _ → Κ ν₀) (λ _ → Κ ν₁)) id (dep-cases (λ _ → ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁)) (λ x y l → l) (dep-cases (λ _ → ι-is-order-preserving ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-order-preserving ν₁)) ι-is-order-preserving (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-order-preserving (Δ ν₀) (Κ ν₀) (λ _ → Δ ν₁) (λ _ → Κ ν₁) (ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁) (ι-is-order-preserving ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-order-preserving ν₁) ι-is-order-preserving (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = pair-fun-is-order-preserving (Δ ν) (Κ ν) (Δ ∘ A) (𝓚 ν A) (ι ν) (λ x → γ x ∘ ι (A x)) (ι-is-order-preserving ν) g where open Κ-extension ν A IH : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) (y z : ⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩) → y ≺⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩ z → ι (A x) y ≺⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ ι (A x) z IH x = ι-is-order-preserving (A x) f : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) (y z : ⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩) → ι (A x) y ≺⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ ι (A x) z → γ x (ι (A x) y) ≺⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ γ x (ι (A x) z) f x y z = inverses-of-order-equivs-are-order-preserving [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (≃ₒ-to-fun-is-order-equiv [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (ϕ x)) (ι (A x) y) (ι (A x) z) g : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) (y z : ⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩) → y ≺⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩ z → γ x (ι (A x) y) ≺⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ γ x (ι (A x) z) g x y z l = f x y z (IH x y z l) ι-is-order-reflecting : (ν : E) (x y : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ι ν x ≺⟨ Κ ν ⟩ ι ν y → x ≺⟨ Δ ν ⟩ y ι-is-order-reflecting ⌜𝟙⌝ = λ x y l → l ι-is-order-reflecting ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ι𝟙ᵒ-is-order-reflecting ι-is-order-reflecting (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-order-reflecting 𝟚ᵒ 𝟚ᵒ (cases (λ _ → Δ ν₀) (λ _ → Δ ν₁)) (cases (λ _ → Κ ν₀) (λ _ → Κ ν₁)) id (dep-cases (λ _ → ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁)) (λ x y l → l) id-is-embedding (dep-cases (λ _ → ι-is-order-reflecting ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-order-reflecting ν₁)) ι-is-order-reflecting (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-order-reflecting (Δ ν₀) (Κ ν₀) (λ _ → Δ ν₁) (λ _ → Κ ν₁) (ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁) (ι-is-order-reflecting ν₀) (ι-is-embedding ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-order-reflecting ν₁) ι-is-order-reflecting (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = pair-fun-is-order-reflecting (Δ ν) (Κ ν) (Δ ∘ A) (𝓚 ν A) (ι ν) (λ x → γ x ∘ ι (A x)) (ι-is-order-reflecting ν) (ι-is-embedding ν) g where open Κ-extension ν A IH : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) (y z : ⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩) → ι (A x) y ≺⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ ι (A x) z → y ≺⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩ z IH x = ι-is-order-reflecting (A x) f : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) (y z : ⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩) → γ x (ι (A x) y) ≺⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ γ x (ι (A x) z) → ι (A x) y ≺⟨ Κ (A x) ⟩ ι (A x) z f x y z = inverses-of-order-equivs-are-order-reflecting [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (≃ₒ-to-fun-is-order-equiv [ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ] [ Κ (A x) ] (ϕ x)) (ι (A x) y) (ι (A x) z) g : (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) (y z : ⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩) → γ x (ι (A x) y) ≺⟨ 𝓚 ν A (ι ν x) ⟩ γ x (ι (A x) z) → y ≺⟨ Δ (A x) ⟩ z g x y z l = IH x y z (f x y z l) ι-is-dense : (ν : E) → is-dense (ι ν) ι-is-dense ⌜𝟙⌝ = id-is-dense ι-is-dense ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = ι𝟙-dense fe₀ ι-is-dense (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-dense id (dep-cases (λ _ → ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁)) id-is-dense (dep-cases (λ _ → ι-is-dense ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-dense ν₁)) ι-is-dense (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-dense _ _ (ι-is-dense ν₀) (λ _ → ι-is-dense ν₁) ι-is-dense (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = pair-fun-dense (ι ν) (λ x → γ x ∘ ι (A x)) (ι-is-dense ν) (λ x → comp-is-dense (ι-is-dense (A x)) (equivs-are-dense' (Γ x))) where open Κ-extension ν A \end{code} The characteristic function of topological limit points. \begin{code} ℓ : (ν : E) → ⟨ Δ ν ⟩ → 𝟚 ℓ ⌜𝟙⌝ ⋆ = ₀ ℓ ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ (inl n) = ₀ ℓ ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ (inr ⋆) = ₁ ℓ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inl ⋆ , x₀) = ℓ ν₀ x₀ ℓ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inr ⋆ , x₁) = ℓ ν₁ x₁ ℓ (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) (x₀ , x₁) = max𝟚 (ℓ ν₀ x₀) (ℓ ν₁ x₁) ℓ (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) (x , y) = max𝟚 (ℓ ν x) (ℓ (A x) y) \end{code} Non-limit points are isolated in the Κ interpretation: \begin{code} ℓ-isolated : (ν : E) (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ℓ ν x = ₀ → is-isolated (ι ν x) ℓ-isolated ⌜𝟙⌝ ⋆ p = 𝟙-is-discrete ⋆ ℓ-isolated ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ (inl n) refl = finite-isolated fe₀ n ℓ-isolated (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inl ⋆ , x₀) p = Σ-isolated (inl-is-isolated ⋆ (𝟙-is-discrete ⋆)) (ℓ-isolated ν₀ x₀ p) ℓ-isolated (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inr ⋆ , x₁) p = Σ-isolated (inr-is-isolated ⋆ (𝟙-is-discrete ⋆)) (ℓ-isolated ν₁ x₁ p) ℓ-isolated (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) (x₀ , x₁) p = Σ-isolated (ℓ-isolated ν₀ x₀ (max𝟚-₀-left p)) (ℓ-isolated ν₁ x₁ (max𝟚-₀-right p)) ℓ-isolated (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) (x , y) p = iv where open Κ-extension ν A i : is-isolated (ι ν x) i = ℓ-isolated ν x (max𝟚-₀-left p) ii : is-isolated (ι (A x) y) ii = ℓ-isolated (A x) y (max𝟚-₀-right p) iii : is-isolated (γ x (ι (A x) y)) iii = equivs-preserve-isolatedness (γ x) (γ-is-equiv x) (ι (A x) y) ii iv : is-isolated (ι ν x , γ x (ι (A x) y)) iv = Σ-isolated i iii \end{code} The function ℓ really does detect limit points: \begin{code} module _ (pe : propext 𝓤₀) where ℓ-limit : (ν : E) (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ℓ ν x = ₁ → is-limit-point (ι ν x) ℓ-limit ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ (inr ⋆) p i = is-isolated-gives-is-isolated' ∞ i ℓ-limit (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inl ⋆ , x₀) p i = ℓ-limit ν₀ x₀ p (Σ-isolated-right (underlying-type-is-setᵀ fe 𝟚ᵒ) i) ℓ-limit (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inr ⋆ , x₁) p i = ℓ-limit ν₁ x₁ p (Σ-isolated-right (underlying-type-is-setᵀ fe 𝟚ᵒ) i) ℓ-limit (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) (x₀ , x₁) p i = Cases (max𝟚-lemma p) (λ (p₀ : ℓ ν₀ x₀ = ₁) → ℓ-limit ν₀ x₀ p₀ (×-isolated-left i)) (λ (p₁ : ℓ ν₁ x₁ = ₁) → ℓ-limit ν₁ x₁ p₁ (×-isolated-right i)) ℓ-limit (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) (x , y) p i = Cases (max𝟚-lemma p) (λ (p₀ : ℓ ν x = ₁) → ℓ-limit ν x p₀ (Σ-isolated-left (𝓚-Compact pe ν A) i)) (λ (p₁ : ℓ (A x) y = ₁) → ℓ-limit (A x) y p₁ (equivs-reflect-isolatedness (γ x) (γ-is-equiv x) (ι (A x) y) (Σ-isolated-right (underlying-type-is-setᵀ fe (Κ ν)) i))) where open Κ-extension ν A isolatedness-decision : (ν : E) (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → is-isolated (ι ν x) + is-limit-point (ι ν x) isolatedness-decision ν x = 𝟚-equality-cases (λ (p : ℓ ν x = ₀) → inl (ℓ-isolated ν x p)) (λ (p : ℓ ν x = ₁) → inr (ℓ-limit ν x p)) isolatedness-decision' : ¬ WLPO → (ν : E) (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → is-decidable (is-isolated (ι ν x)) isolatedness-decision' f ν x = Cases (isolatedness-decision ν x) inl (λ (g : is-isolated (ι ν x) → WLPO) → inr (contrapositive g f)) \end{code} Added 14th October 2024. Actually we have that a stronger property of limit point holds. \begin{code} ℓ-limit⁺ : (ν : E) (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ℓ ν x = ₁ → is-limit-point⁺ (ι ν x) ℓ-limit⁺ ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ (inr x) p i = ∞-is-a-limit-point⁺-of-ℕ∞ fe₀ i ℓ-limit⁺ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inl ⋆ , x₀) p i = ℓ-limit⁺ ν₀ x₀ p (Σ-weakly-isolated-right (underlying-type-is-setᵀ fe 𝟚ᵒ) i) ℓ-limit⁺ (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) (inr ⋆ , x₁) p i = ℓ-limit⁺ ν₁ x₁ p (Σ-weakly-isolated-right (underlying-type-is-setᵀ fe 𝟚ᵒ) i) ℓ-limit⁺ (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) (x₀ , x₁) p i = Cases (max𝟚-lemma p) (λ (p₀ : ℓ ν₀ x₀ = ₁) → ℓ-limit⁺ ν₀ x₀ p₀ (×-weakly-isolated-left i)) (λ (p₁ : ℓ ν₁ x₁ = ₁) → ℓ-limit⁺ ν₁ x₁ p₁ (×-weakly-isolated-right i)) ℓ-limit⁺ (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) (x , y) p i = Cases (max𝟚-lemma p) (λ (p₀ : ℓ ν x = ₁) → ℓ-limit⁺ ν x p₀ (Σ-weakly-isolated-left (𝓚-Compact pe ν A) i)) (λ (p₁ : ℓ (A x) y = ₁) → ℓ-limit⁺ (A x) y p₁ (equivs-reflect-weak-isolatedness (Γ x) (ι (A x) y) (Σ-weakly-isolated-right (underlying-type-is-setᵀ fe (Κ ν)) i))) where open Κ-extension ν A \end{code} End of addition and back to the past. We conclude with some impossibility results. \begin{code} ι-is-equiv-gives-LPO : ((ν : E) → is-equiv (ι ν)) → LPO ι-is-equiv-gives-LPO f = ι𝟙-is-equiv-gives-LPO (f ⌜ω+𝟙⌝) LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv : LPO → (ν : E) → is-equiv (ι ν) LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ⌜𝟙⌝ = id-is-equiv 𝟙 LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ⌜ω+𝟙⌝ = LPO-gives-ι𝟙-is-equiv fe₀ lpo LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo (ν₀ ⌜+⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-equiv id (dep-cases (λ _ → ι ν₀) (λ _ → ι ν₁)) (id-is-equiv (𝟙 + 𝟙)) (dep-cases (λ _ → LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ν₀) (λ _ → LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ν₁)) LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo (ν₀ ⌜×⌝ ν₁) = pair-fun-is-equiv _ _ (LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ν₀) (λ _ → LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ν₁) LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo (⌜Σ⌝ ν A) = pair-fun-is-equiv (ι ν) (λ x → γ x ∘ ι (A x)) (LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ν) (λ x → ∘-is-equiv (LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo (A x)) (γ-is-equiv x)) where open Κ-extension ν A ι-is-equiv-iff-LPO : ((ν : E) → is-equiv (ι ν)) ↔ LPO ι-is-equiv-iff-LPO = ι-is-equiv-gives-LPO , LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv \end{code} We also have the following: \begin{code} ι-has-section-gives-Κ-discrete : (ν : E) → has-section (ι ν) → is-discrete ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ ι-has-section-gives-Κ-discrete ν (θ , ιθ) = lc-maps-reflect-discreteness θ (sections-are-lc θ (ι ν , ιθ)) (Δ-is-discrete ν) ι-is-equiv-gives-Κ-discrete : (ν : E) → is-equiv (ι ν) → is-discrete ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ ι-is-equiv-gives-Κ-discrete ν e = ι-has-section-gives-Κ-discrete ν (equivs-have-sections (ι ν) e) LPO-gives-Κ-discrete : LPO → (ν : E) → is-discrete ⟨ Κ ν ⟩ LPO-gives-Κ-discrete lpo ν = ι-is-equiv-gives-Κ-discrete ν (LPO-gives-ι-is-equiv lpo ν) Κ-discrete-gives-WLPO : ((ν : E) → is-discrete ⟨ Κ ν ⟩) → WLPO Κ-discrete-gives-WLPO f = ℕ∞-discrete-gives-WLPO (f ⌜ω+𝟙⌝) \end{code} We close with some open questions. TODO. Can we close the gap between the last two facts? The difficulty that arises here is similar to the following. Let P be a proposition and assume function extensionality. (0) If P is decidable, then the function type (P → 𝟚) has decidable equality. (1) If (P → 𝟚) has decidable equality, then ¬ P is decidable. It doesn't seem to be possible to reverse any of the implications (0) and (1), so that the proposition "(P -> 2) has decidable equality" seems to be strictly between "P is decidable" and "¬P is decidable". This is discussed in the following module. \begin{code} import Taboos.P2 \end{code} TODO. Do we have (ν : E) → [ Δ ν ] ⊴ [ Κ ν ]? Notice that we do have (ω +ₒ 𝟙ₒ) ⊴ ℕ∞ₒ, proved in the following module. \begin{code} import Ordinals.ConvergentSequence \end{code} TODO. Define an element x of an ordinal to be trisolated if for every y we have that y ≺ x or x = y or x ≺ y. Notice that trisolated elements are isolated. Define an ordinal to be trichotomous if every element is trisolated. We should have the following: ℓ-trisolated : (ν : E) (x : ⟨ Δ ν ⟩) → ℓ ν x = ₀ → is-trisolated (ι ν x) We don't need to discuss the case ℓ ν x = ₁ because this is already covered by ℓ-limit as trisolated points are isolated. TODO. An element x of α is trisolated iff there are ordinals αₕ and αₜ and an ordinal-equivalence αₕ +ₒ 𝟙ₒ + αₜ → α that maps the point at the component 𝟙ₒ to x. TODO. Suprema of compact ordinals are compact. (This follows directly from the constructions in the file OrdinalOfOrdinalsSupremum.) TODO. Are the ordinals in the image of K totally separated? TODO. The map ℓ should also be the characteristic function of ordinal-limit points.