Martin Escardo 27th Nov 2013, last updated 4th Dec 2013, ported to this repository 2nd June 2023 In intensional Martin-Löf type theory, if all functions (ℕ → ℕ) → ℕ are continuous, then 0 = 1 1. Introduction 2. Informal proof of the theorem 3. Formal proof in Agda notation 4. Discussion References Introduction ------------ In Brouwer's intuitionistic mathematics, it can be proved that all functions f : (ℕ → ℕ) → ℕ are continuous [5]. This means that the value f(α) depends only on a finite prefix of the infinite sequence α : ℕ → ℕ. Then, of course, Brouwer's mathematics is incompatible with excluded middle, as excluded middle easily defines non-continuous functions. Intensional Martin-Löf type theory (MLTT) [2] is an alternative foundation for constructive mathematics [5]. Like Bishop's constructive mathematics [5], it is compatible with classical mathematics. It doesn't prove or disprove excluded middle, which can be consistently postulated, albeit with loss of computational content, for the purposes of developing classical mathematics. In the version of (intensional) MLTT considered here, we have identity types Id X x y (written x = y and called propositional equality), some basic types such as that of natural numbers (written ℕ) and that of finite sequences of natural numbers of length n (written Vec ℕ n), and dependent type constructors Π (written ∀) and Σ. We have the eliminator J for identity types, but not Streicher's eliminator K, and we don't have the equality reflection rule. We don't have the axiom of function extensionality (any two pointwise equal functions are equal). A possible formulation of continuity in MLTT under the so-called BHK (Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov) interpretation Σ of the quantifier ∃ is ∀(α : ℕ → ℕ), Σ n : ℕ , ∀(β : ℕ → ℕ) , α =[n] β → f(α) = f(β), where α =[n] β means that the sequences α and β agree at the first n positions. We show in MLTT that, with this formulation of continuity, if all functions f : (ℕ → ℕ) → ℕ are continuous, then 0 = 1. We write the proof both informally and formally in Agda notation [3]. See Bauer [1] for a related well-known phenomenon with the same proof ingredients used here. We emphasize that our proof doesn't use the axiom of function extensionality (any two pointwise equal functions are equal), which anyway is not available in MLTT (but is in Homotopy Type Theory (HoTT)). It also doesn't require universes. In HoTT [2], there is an alternative constructive existential quantifier, written ∃, corresponding to the topos theoretic existential quantifier, in which witnesses are hidden, but can be disclosed via unique choice, formulated as the axiom of description by Coquand [6]. Brouwer's continuity axiom with Σ replaced by ∃ is consistent with MLTT, even when MLTT is extended with the axiom of function extensionality. Hopefully it is compatible with the HoTT extensions of MLTT too, but this is an open problem. 2. Informal proof of the theorem -------------------------------- The proof in this section is the informal rendering of the formal proof given in Section 3 below. It is based on a proof attributed to van Dalen and Troelstra by Bauer [1] for a different theorem. Write Baire = ℕ → ℕ to denote the type of sequences, and let 0^ω = the infinite sequence of zeros, and 0^n k^ω = the sequence of n many zeros followed by infinitely many k's. Then (0^n k^ω) =[n] 0^ω and (0^n k^ω)(n) = k. Assume that all functions are continuous, with the Σ-formulation of continuity as in the introduction: ∀(f : Baire → ℕ). ∀(α : Baire). Σ(n : ℕ). ∀(β : Baire). α =[n] β → f(α) = f(β). By projection, with α = 0^ω, this gives a modulus-of-continuity function M : (Baire → ℕ) → ℕ such that ∀ (f : Baire → ℕ) , ∀ (β : Baire) , 0^ω =[M f] β → f(0^ω) = f(β). (0) We use M to define a non-continuous function f : Baire → ℕ and hence get a contradiction. What this really says is that no such function M can be continuous. See the discussion in Section 4 below. Notice also that if we were using ∃ rather than Σ to define continuity, as discussed in the introduction, we would need choice to get M. Let m = M (λ α. 0), and define f : Baire → ℕ by f β = M (λ α. β (α m)). Observe that, by simply expanding the definitions, with the understanding that 0^ω defined above is λ i. 0, f(0^ω) = m. By the defining property (0) of M, ∀(β : Baire). 0^ω =[ M f ] β → m = f β. (1) Case 0. M f = 0. ------ By (1), ∀(β : Baire). m = f β. The choice β i = i gives m = f(λ i. i) = M (λ α. α m). By the defining property (0) of M, this means that ∀(α : Baire). 0^ω =[ m ] α → 0 = α m. But this gives 0 = 1 if we choose e.g. the sequence α = 0^m 1^ω. Case 1. M f > 0. ------ For any β : Baire, by the continuity of λ α. β (α m), by the definition of f, and by the defining property (0) of M, we have that ∀(α : Baire). 0^ω =[ f β ] α → β 0 = β (α m). Considering β = 0^(M f) 1^ω, this gives ∀(α : Baire). 0^ω =[ m ] α → β 0 = β (α m), because f β = m as 0^ω =[ M f ] β and f(0^ω) = m. Considering α = 0^m (M f)^ω, this in turn gives 0 = β 0 = β (α m) = β (M f) = 1. Q.E.D. 3. Formal proof in Agda notation -------------------------------- The main reason for giving a formal proof is to be certain that the above argument doesn't use function extensionality (any two pointwise equal functions are equal) inadvertently. 3.1. Standard preliminary definitions ------------------------------------- The option without-K is used to disable the UIP (uniqueness of identity proofs) principle, also known as Streicher's Axiom K, which is not part of MLTT: \begin{code} {-# OPTIONS --safe --without-K #-} module ContinuityAxiom.False where open import MLTT.Spartan open import MLTT.Vector Baire : 𝓤₀ ̇ Baire = ℕ → ℕ _⟦_⟧ : {X : 𝓤 ̇} → (ℕ → X) → (n : ℕ) → Vector X n α ⟦ 0 ⟧ = [] α ⟦ succ n ⟧ = α 0 ∷ ((λ i → α (succ i)) ⟦ n ⟧) _=⟦_⟧_ : {X : 𝓤₀ ̇} → (ℕ → X) → ℕ → (ℕ → X) → 𝓤₀ ̇ α =⟦ n ⟧ β = α ⟦ n ⟧ = β ⟦ n ⟧ \end{code} The above definitions are standard in type theory/constructive mathematics. The second last one takes a finite prefix of a given length of a given infinite sequence, and hence the last one defines when two given sequences agree at the first n positions. 3.2 Formulation of the theorem ------------------------------ The following is Brouwer's definition of continuity, formulated with Σ rather than ∃: \begin{code} continuous : (Baire → ℕ) → 𝓤₀ ̇ continuous f = (α : Baire) → Σ n ꞉ ℕ , ((β : Baire) → α =⟦ n ⟧ β → f α = f β) \end{code} In Brouwer's mathematics, all functions are continuous, but this can't be true if continuity is (incorrectly) formulated with Σ as above: \begin{code} theorem : ((f : Baire → ℕ) → continuous f) → 0 = 1 \end{code} We need some preparation to prove that. 3.3 Preliminary proofs and constructions ---------------------------------------- The following is standard in MLTT: For future reference, notice that all uses of ap below are for (first-order) functions of types ℕ → ℕ vec ℕ (succ n) → ℕ vec ℕ n → vec ℕ (succ n) only. The following definition of (n zeros-and-then k) gives a sequence of n many zeros followed by k and then by something irrelevant (infinitely many k's, in fact, but we don't need to know that): \begin{code} _zeros-and-then_ : ℕ → ℕ → Baire ( 0 zeros-and-then k) i = k ((succ n) zeros-and-then k) 0 = 0 ((succ n) zeros-and-then k) (succ i) = (n zeros-and-then k) i o : Baire o = λ i → 0 zeros-and-then-spec₀ : (n k : ℕ) → (n zeros-and-then k) n = k zeros-and-then-spec₀ 0 k = refl zeros-and-then-spec₀ (succ n) k = zeros-and-then-spec₀ n k zeros-and-then-spec₁ : (n k : ℕ) → o =⟦ n ⟧ (n zeros-and-then k) zeros-and-then-spec₁ n k = zeros₀ n ∙ zeros₁ n k where zeros : (n : ℕ) → Vector ℕ n zeros 0 = [] zeros (succ n) = 0 ∷ zeros n zeros₀ : (n : ℕ) → o ⟦ n ⟧ = zeros n zeros₀ 0 = refl zeros₀ (succ n) = ap (λ ns → 0 ∷ ns) (zeros₀ n) zeros₁ : (n k : ℕ) → zeros n = (n zeros-and-then k) ⟦ n ⟧ zeros₁ 0 k = refl zeros₁ (succ n) k = ap (λ ns → 0 ∷ ns) (zeros₁ n k) \end{code} 3.4 Proof of the theorem ------------------------ Finally, here is the proof of the claim. It uses the modulus of continuity functional M such that M f is a modulus of continuity at the constant zero sequence o (defined above), which exists because we are using the existential quantifier Σ rather than ∃ in our (unsatisfactory) definition of continuity, in order to define a non-continuous function f and hence get a contradiction. Recall that our goal is to prove theorem : ((f : Baire → ℕ) → continuous f) → 0 = 1 formulated above in Agda. \begin{code} theorem continuity = γ where M : (Baire → ℕ) → ℕ M f = pr₁ (continuity f o) continuity₀ : (f : Baire → ℕ) (β : Baire) → o =⟦ M f ⟧ β → f o = f β continuity₀ f = pr₂ (continuity f o) m : ℕ m = M (λ α → 0) f : Baire → ℕ f β = M (λ α → β (α m)) observation : f o = m observation = refl fact₀ : (β : Baire) → o =⟦ M f ⟧ β → m = f β fact₀ = continuity₀ f lemma₀ : M f = 0 → 0 = 1 lemma₀ r = 0 =⟨ claim₄ α (zeros-and-then-spec₁ m 1) ⟩ α m =⟨ α-fact₀ ⟩ 1 ∎ where claim₀ : (β : Baire) → m = f β claim₀ β = fact₀ β claim₁ where claim₁ : o =⟦ M f ⟧ β claim₁ = transport (λ - → o =⟦ - ⟧ β) (r ⁻¹) refl claim₂ : m = M (λ α → α m) claim₂ = claim₀ (λ i → i) claim₃ : (α : Baire) → o =⟦ M (λ α → α m) ⟧ α → 0 = α m claim₃ = continuity₀ (λ α → α m) claim₄ : (α : Baire) → o =⟦ m ⟧ α → 0 = α m claim₄ = transport (λ - → (α : Baire) → o =⟦ - ⟧ α → 0 = α m) (claim₂ ⁻¹) claim₃ α : Baire α = m zeros-and-then 1 α-fact₀ : α m = 1 α-fact₀ = zeros-and-then-spec₀ m 1 lemma₁ : (Σ n ꞉ ℕ , M f = succ n) → 0 = 1 lemma₁ (n , r) = 0 =⟨ claim (transport (λ - → o =⟦ - ⟧ β) r β-fact₁) ⟩ β 0 =⟨ fact₄ ⟩ 1 ∎ where β : Baire β = (M f) zeros-and-then 1 β-fact₀ : β (M f) = 1 β-fact₀ = zeros-and-then-spec₀ (M f) 1 β-fact₁ : o =⟦ M f ⟧ β β-fact₁ = zeros-and-then-spec₁ (M f) 1 fact₀' : f β = m fact₀' = (fact₀ β β-fact₁)⁻¹ fact₁ : (α : Baire) → o =⟦ f β ⟧ α → β 0 = β (α m) fact₁ α = continuity₀ (λ α → β (α m)) α fact₂ : (α : Baire) → o =⟦ m ⟧ α → β 0 = β (α m) fact₂ = transport (λ n → (α : Baire) → o =⟦ n ⟧ α → β 0 = β (α m)) fact₀' fact₁ α : Baire α = m zeros-and-then (M f) α-fact₀ : α m = M f α-fact₀ = zeros-and-then-spec₀ m (M f) α-fact₁ : o =⟦ m ⟧ α α-fact₁ = zeros-and-then-spec₁ m (M f) fact₃ : β 0 = β (α m) fact₃ = fact₂ α α-fact₁ fact₄ : β 0 = 1 fact₄ = β 0 =⟨ fact₃ ⟩ β (α m) =⟨ ap β α-fact₀ ⟩ β (M f) =⟨ β-fact₀ ⟩ 1 ∎ claim : o =⟦ succ n ⟧ β → 0 = β 0 claim = ap head lemma : (Σ n ꞉ ℕ , M f = n) → 0 = 1 lemma (0 , r) = lemma₀ r lemma (succ n , r) = lemma₁ (n , r) γ : 0 = 1 γ = lemma (M f , refl) \end{code} 4. Discussion ------------- For a large research community, the terminology "extensionality" usually refers to the rule x = y implies f x = f y, which here is called "ap" and defined above. This form of extensionality is a feature of intensional type theory, and can be regarded as a property of identity types. A red herring in connection with Andrej Bauer's post [1] is that the "extensionality" of M, that is, the availability of the function ap _ _ M of type f = g → M f = M g, is not used in the above proof. We only use the "extensionality" of first-order functions. However, one of these functions, namely β, is defined indirectly from M, and so its "extensionality" relies on that of M, at least loosely speaking. What is important is that we don't use the so-called axiom of function extensionality (any two pointwise equal functions are equal), which is not available in intensional type theory. The fundamental reason for the contradiction is a topological phenomenon: there can't be any continuous modulus-of-continuity functional M. No finite part of a continuous function f : (ℕ → ℕ) → ℕ is enough to tell which finite part of α : ℕ → ℕ is sufficient to determine f(α). In fact, what the above proof does is to use the hypothetical M to construct a non-continuous function f. In the topological topos all functions Baire → ℕ are continuous, both externally and internally, but there is no continuous M. The right notion of continuity, which is validated in some models, is ∀ (f : Baire → ℕ) , ∀(α : Baire) , ∥ Σ n : ℕ , ∀ (β : Baire), α =⟦ n ⟧ β → f α = f β ∥, where we use propositional truncation (or bracket types), which can be written, using HoTT notation [2], as ∀ (f : Baire → ℕ) , ∀ (α : Baire) , ∃ n : ℕ) , ∀ (β : Baire) , α =⟦ n ⟧ β → f α = f β. This implies the weaker statement ∀ (f : Baire → ℕ) , ∀ (α : Baire) , ¬¬Σ n : ℕ , ∀ (β : Baire), α =⟦ n ⟧ β → f α = f β, which can be expressed without hpropositional truncation and hence in MLTT. It is an interesting problem whether the ∃-formulation of continuity can be formulated in pure MLTT (with or without universes). Both the ∃-version and the ¬¬Σ version are validated in the topological topos interpretation and hence are consistent. Notice that a topos has both ∃ (via the subobject classifier) and Σ (via its local cartesian closed structure). What the above says is that continuity formulated with Σ is false in any topos, but continuity formulated with ∃ holds in some toposes. This is similar to the fact that the axiom of choice formulated with Σ holds in any topos, but often fails when formulated with ∃. Other continuity axioms that hold in Browerian mathematics do admit a consistent Σ formulation in MLTT, such as uniform continuity ∀(f : Cantor → ℕ).Σ(n : ℕ).∀(α β : Cantor). α =⟦ n ⟧ β → f α = f β, where Cantor is the type of infinite binary sequences [4]. References ---------- [0] This file is available in two forms: http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~mhe/continuity-false/continuity-false.lagda http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~mhe/continuity-false/continuity-false.html [1] Andrej Bauer. http://math.andrej.com/2011/07/27/definability-and-extensionality-of-the-modulus-of-continuity-functional/ [2] The HoTT Book. http://homotopytypetheory.org/book/ Chapter 1 introduces intensional MLTT without its homotopical extensions. The appendix gives a formal treatment of MLTT with and without the extensions. [3] The Agda Wiki. http://wiki.portal.chalmers.se/agda/pmwiki.php [4] Chuangjie Xu and M.H. Escardó. A constructive model of uniform continuity. M. Hasegawa (Ed.): TLCA 2013, LNCS 7941, pp. 236-249. Springer, Heidelberg 2013. [4'] M.H. Escardó and Chuangjie Xu. A constructive manifestation of the Kleene-Kreisel continuous functionals. Submitted. http://www.cs.bham.ac.uk/~mhe/papers/kleene-kreisel.pdf [5] M. Beeson. Foundations of Constructive Mathematics: Metamathematical Studies, Springer, Berlin/Heidelberg/New York, 1985. [6] T. Coquand. Type Theory and Univalent Foundation. Royal Society meeting, 26 Nov 2013. http://www.cse.chalmers.se/~coquand/rs.pdf